REMINDER - "REID"S READER" NOW APPEARS FORTNIGHTLY RATHER THAN WEEKLY.
We feature each week Nicholas Reid's reviews and comments on new and recent books.
“ENLIGHTENMENT NOW” by Steven
Pinker (Penguin/Random House – Allen Lane, $NZ40)
After
I had finished reading Steven Pinker’s new big polemic Enlightenment Now (453 pages of text followed by 100 pages of
endnotes, bibliography and index), I went back and checked on this blog the
review I wrote, seven years ago, of his last big polemic The Better Angels of Our Nature. I found that I approved and had
reservations about that earlier book in more-or-less the same proportions, and
for the same reasons, as I do with Pinker’s new book. Put simply, Enlightenment Now (subtitled “The Case
for Reason, Science, Humanism and Progress”) makes a very good case for the
notion that the human condition has been greatly improved thanks to
Enlightenment thinking and applied science. “Progress” is a great thing. But
Pinker over-eggs his pudding by a very selective and partisan reading of
history; and he has the dire habit of dividing our intellectual forebears into
neat heroes and villains, a Manichaean view of history as simple
black-and-white. As a lesser irritant Pinker also tends to see America as the
template for the world – the copious statistics he quotes focus most on America
– and there is a very hortatory tone to the book as if Pinker is not only the
apologist for the Enlightenment but also its cheer-leader, much as he is a
cheer-leader for liberal capitalism
But
it is very unfair to arraign a polemicist for his sins before first presenting
clearly the case that he makes.
So
here, as I read it, is Harvard
psychology professor Steven Pinker’s
case.
Nature
of itself tends to entropy – the degeneration of things into disorder and
confusion. Only the human intellect can avert this pending state. The finest
flowering of the human intellect began with the movement – initiated
approximately three centuries ago – generally known as the Enlightenment. From
the Enlightenment come nearly all the measurable material improvements in human
life that can loosely be called “progress”. Progress and its handmaid
technology have their intellectual enemies (see Chapter 4, “Progressophobia”).
But, says Pinker, the case for progress is overwhelming. Thus in sixteen chapters
(Chapters 5 to 20), and using his favourite tool, the statistical graph, Pinker
sets out to prove how everything has got better in the last three centuries. On
average, we live longer, have better health and enjoy plentiful and more varied
food than we did in the un-Enlightened ages (Chapters 5, 6 and 7). Wealth has
generally increased and this is not compromised by the fact that there is still
great inequality (Chapters 8 and 9). Despite ecological fears, our environment
is cleaner and there are means of dealing with threats like anthropogenic
global warming (Chapter 10). Despite the image created by alarmist mass media,
wars are fewer than they once were, as is social violence, and the dangers of
terrorism are vastly overrated (Chapters 11, 12 and 13). Real democracy is
growing, human rights are more respected and a greater number of human beings
have education and access to real information than in any earlier period of
history (Chapters 14, 15 and 16). Our general quality of life has improved, as
have all measurable standards of happiness (Chapters 17 and 18). Yes, there may
possibly be huge existential threats that could obliterate the Earth; but we
are better equipped to deal with them than we have ever been (Chapter 19) and
“progress” is far from being exhausted (Chapter 20). All this is thanks to
science, the secularism initiated by the Enlightenment and the decline of
religious belief.
In
a nutshell, this is Pinker’s case.
For
ease of your reading, I will now divide this notice neatly into two parts, to
wit, the strengths and shrewd points of Pinker’s thesis; and the weaknesses and
short-sightedness of elements of Pinker’s thesis.
THE
POSITIVES OF ENLIGHTENMENT NOW
There
is much in this book with which any reader, regardless of ideology, should be
able to agree. First, that the Enlightenment was a major turning point in human
history. Second, that many of the scientific and social changes it encouraged
have benefitted humanity. Of course I am grateful that I consult a modern
doctor rather than a shaman, that medicine is now so advanced, that I enjoy
electricity and easy access to learning and entertainment, that on the whole human
and civil rights are expected to be observed, that more of the world is better
fed and many other things.
Certainly
Pinker’s relentlessly positive tone can become oppressive and tend to the
Pollyanna-ish, as when, following a
graph charting “Global well-being, 1820-1915” there comes the statement “although the world remains highly unequal,
every region has been improving, and the worst-off parts of the world today are
better off than the best-off parts not long ago. (If we divide the world into
the West and the Rest, we find that the Rest in 2007 had reached the level of
the West in 1950.)” (Chapter 16,
p.246). This seems to me to underrate a lot of human misery.
Certainly
Pinker can come up with arguments that seem controversial; but on reflection
they are quite tenable. For example, in Chapter
9 (pp.98-99) he argues that poverty is the world’s problem, not inequality and he
agrees with Harry Frankfurt that “If a
person lives a long, pleasurable, and stimulating life, then how much money the
Joneses earn, how big their house is, and how many cars they drive are morally
irrelevant.” For Pinker, the
important thing is that each has enough. His conclusion is that income
inequality is not the same as lowering incomes and does not contradict his
statistics on the general rise in standards of living. It is interesting to
note, too, that Pinker is in favour of a universal basic income.
To
Pinker’s great credit, however, he is not a utopian and he admits that he is
dealing with averages rather than with absolutes. In the chapter called “The
Future of Progress”, he quotes figures on the milions who still suffer from
poverty, lethal diseases, war and autocratic states and he states “progress is not utopia… and there is room – indeed, an imperative – for
us to strive to continue… progress.” (Chapter 20, pp.325-326)
Like
anybody who reads this book, I have to admit, too, that I warmed most to Pinker
in those sections where he expresses views with which I am already in
agreement.
Pinker
strikes many justifiable blows against various doomsayers. For example, in Chapter
7, and especially at pp.74-75, he shows how completely wrong Malthus, and
alarmists like Paul Ehlich in his hysterical 1968 bestseller The Population Bomb, were about growth
of population outstripping food supply. Their predictions were, quite simply,
wrong and they did not take account of the agricultural revolution which has
vastly increased the yield of crops and made most of the world better fed than
it was when total population was much smaller. Yet, as Pinker correctly says,
there are still those who imagine, regardless of the evidence, that Malthus,
Ehlich et al. have said the last word on the topic. In this same chapter,
Pinker is – again justifiably - very hard on those environmentalists who oppose
genetic engineering without recognising that human beings have practised it for
millennia, and who thus show indifference to the alternative of mass starvation.
Chapter
10 tells us that the “Green apocalyse” has not yet happened. It argues that
anthropogenic climate change is real but is capable of being reversed by wise
policies and advanced technology. Hence Pinker argues strongly against Naomi
Klein’s polemic This Changes Everything [reviewed
on this blog in 2014], which said impending environmental doom called for the complete
destruction of the capitalist system. Says Pinker:
“Despite a half-century of panic, humanity is
not on an irrevocable path to ecological suicide. The fear of resource
shortages is misconceived. So is the misanthropic environmentalism that sees
modern humans as vile despoilers of a pristine planet. An enlightened
environmentalism recognises that humans need to use energy to lift themselves
out of the poverty to which entropy and evolution consign them. It seeks to do
so with the least harm to the planet and the living world. History suggests
that this modern, pragmatic and humanistic environmentalism can work.” (Chapter 10, p.154)
It
is important to note that, considering “clean” and cheap methods of power
generation, Pinker says some favourable things about nuclear power.
I
warm most to Pinker when he attacks malign intellectual trends, some of which
have taken root in academe. Considering measurable intelligence he says,
correctly: “The myth, still popular among
leftist intellectuals, that IQ doesn’t exist or cannot be reliably measured was
refuted decades ago.” (Chapter 16, p.243) He is aware that the comforts and
conveniences of life in an advanced state lead people to over-estimate the
troubles they face. He quotes with approval the psychologist Richard McNally,
who said “Civilians who underwent the terror
of World War II, especially Nazi death factories… would surely be puzzled to
learn that having a wisdom tooth extracted, encountering obnoxious jokes at
work, or giving birth to a healthy baby after an uncomplicated delivery can
cause Post-Traumatic Stress Disorder”. Pinker himself goes on to say “By the same shift, the label ‘depression’
today may be applied to conditions that in the past were called grief, sorrow
or sadness.” (Chapter 18, p.281)
Most
malign intellectual trend of all, of course, is the nonsense of postmodernism. In
the chapter entitled “Reason”, Pinker is mainly concerned with what he sees as
the enemies of reason. He indicts “the
postmodernist credo that reason is a pretext to exert power, reality is
socially constructed, and all statements are trapped in a web of self-reference
and collapse into paradox.” (Chapter 21, p.351) He also makes the
interesting point that when it comes to many issues involving science – such as
anthropogenic climate change – people who admit to its existence and people who
deny its existence are not divided by how well they understand the science, but
by their political ideology and whom they trust. (Chapter 21, p.357). In
effect, he is admitting a point I tried to make somewhat clumsily a few years
ago on this blog, in a posting I called SecularSuperstition. To hold an allegiance to science is not the same as being
scientifically informed, meaning that a great mass of people respect “authority”
just as they did in pre-Enlightenment days.
Naturally
Pinker is very angry at those who blame science itself for the world’s woes,
and again this allows him to take another mighty whack at the postmodernist
school. Thus he speaks of:
“a demonization campaign which impugns science (together with reason
and other Enlightenment values) for crimes that are as old as civilisation,
including racism, slavery, conquest, and genocide. This was a major theme of
the influential Critical Theory of the Frankfurt School, the quasi-Marxist
movement originated by Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer, who proclaimed that
‘the fully enlightened earth radiates disaster triumphant’. It also figures in
the works of postmodernist theorists such as Michel Foucault, who argued that
the Holocaust was the inevitable culmination of a ‘bio-politics’ that began with
the Enlightenment, when science and rational governance exerted increasing
power over people’s lives. In a similar vein, the sociologist Zygmunt Bauman
blamed the Holocaust on the Enlightenment ideal to ‘remake the society, force
it to conform to an overall, scientifically conceived plan.’ In this twisted
narrative, the Nazis themselves are let off the hook (‘It’s modernity’s
fault!’). So is the Nazis’ rabidly counter-Enlightenment ideology, which
despised the degenerate liberal bourgeois worship of reason and progress and
embraced an organic, pagan vitality which drove the struggle between races.” (Chapter 22, pp. 396-397)
I
could cite many other proof-texts to show where I agree with Pinker, but this
process will become wearisome to you, so I will add one last one. Though he is
clearly very uncomfortable in Donald Trump’s United States, and though he has
absolutely no time for the nationalist and racist populism of the extreme
right, Pinker has the intellectual honesty to note that populism is an
ailment of both left and right:
“Populism comes in left-wing and right-wing
varieties, which share a folk-theory of economics as zero-sum competition:
between economic classes in the case of the left, between nations of ethnic
groups in the case of the right. Problems are not seen as challenges that are
inevitable in an indifferent universe but as the malevolent designs of insidious
elites, minorities and foreigners.”
(Chapter 20, p.334)
I
hope this is enough to show that I have read Pinker’s book with an open mind
and, on many issues, with a willingness to agree with him.
Alas,
we now come to the second part of this review.
THE NEGATIVES OF ENLIGHTENMENT NOW
There is something in the very tone of Pinker’s work that
should put us on guard. He is so determined to tell us how well-off we now are,
in contrast with earlier eras, that he frequently rebukes us for not being more
grateful. He is offended that so many people do not genuflect in wonderment at
the technologically-advanced, humane, Enlightenment-influenced world we live
in. He is doubly offended that so many people cannot make Enlightenment ideas
themselves the focus and centre of their being.
Why should this so clearly offend Pinker? Partly, I
think, because as a devout atheist (he happily speaks at “Freedom from
Religion” meetings) he is very loath to acknowledge the “God-sized hole” in
modern human consciousness (a term which, of course, he despises). I must use
my words very carefully here. I accept fully the idea that people can have
fulfilling, meaningful and satisfying lives without in any way being religious.
Indeed I accept that reasoned atheism can be meaningful and satisfying, and
become a goal in itself. Even so, when personal autonomy is posited as the
essential goal of life (see Chapter 18, p.265), we have a disconnect from our
fellow human beings and much alienation. Much as we are grateful for them, all
the material comforts in the world cannot solve this problem. Indeed, I wonder
if Pinker would have even written this polemic if he had not been jibed by the fact
that greatly improved material progress has still left many in advanced
countries with a sense of emptiness which he is unhappy to recognise and which, for his own ideological reasons, he is unwilling to acknowledge?
Further to this, I think Pinker is annoyed at the
phenomenon I have elsewhere called the “law of mundanity”. In the chapter
called “Quality of Life”, Pinker tells us we should be happy for having more
varied diets, more leisure time, more access to great literature. He continues:
“What are the people doing with the extra
time and money?Are they truly enriching their lives or are they just buying
more golf clubs and designer handbags? Though it’s presumptuous to pass
judgment on how people choose to spend their days, we can focus on the pursuits
that almost everyone would agree are constituents of the good life: connecting
with loved ones and friends, experiencing the richness of the natural and
cultural world, and having access to the fruits of intellectual and artisitc
creativity.” (Chapter 17, p. 255)
But
here the “law of mundanity” kicks in. In any era, no matter how well off we
are, the daily reality we live with becomes taken-for-granted normality. This
is as true in wealthy, well-fed, violence-free societies as in any other. (I do
not say this to deny the desirability of material well-being.) Hence we do not
sigh each day in amazement and gratitude that we have flush-lavatories and
excellent plumbing, reliable medicine, good food etc.etc. “Law of mundanity”.
It is a feature of being human, and Steven Pinker can neither reason nor hector
us out of it by telling us, like a careworn mother, to eat our food and be
grateful.
Pinker
has a very skewed and limited view of history and of how what he would call “progress”
actually happens. This is bound up with his view of religion. For him, religion
(along with the Romantic movement) is part of what he calls the “counter-Enlightenment”,
and is characterised solely by obscurantism, crusades, inquisitions, wars of
religion etc. Of all the opponents of Enlightenment, he says, “the most obvious is religious faith. To take
something on faith means to believe it without good reason, so by definition a
faith in the existence of supernatural entities clashes with reason.”
(Chapter 3, p.30) He is therefore bound to assume that religion cannot go with
reason, and by extension that religious people are prone to being unreasonable.
They therefore cannot be part of his version of Enlightenment.
But he is then forced into some fancy footwork when
having to face up to the fact that avowedly atheist regimes in our own times have
been responsible for huge atrocities. So he claims “obviously atheism is not a moral system in the first place. It’s just
the absence of supernatural belief… the moral alternative to theism is humanism.”
(Chapter 23, p.430) (In passing one notes that he uses the term “humanism” is a
very restricted sense, never once noting that the term was first used in the
Renaissance – a term that never appears in this book – of mainly Christian
thinkers like Erasmus and Thomas More.) The result appears to be that Pinker
approves of no religious believers and only of those atheists who share all his
world view. There is a great defensiveness to this argument, as there is in Chapter
22 (“Science”) when Pinker attempts to extricate science from such negative
movements as eugenics.
Most
obviously, however, the result of Pinker’s bias is to expunge from his record
such religious believers as have contributed to what we would agree is the
betterment of humanity. Here is Pinker on evolution:
“Organisms
are replete with improbable configurations of flesh like ears, eyes, hearts and
stomachs which cry out for an explanation. Before Charles Darwin and Alfred
Russel Wallace provided one in 1859, it was reasonable to think that they were
the handiwork of a divine designer – one of the reasons, I suspect, that so
many Enlightenment thinkers were deists rather than outright atheists. Darwin
and Wallace made the designer unnecessary.” (Chapter 2, p.18) As one who
accepts evolution by natural selection as the best hypothesis we have for the
development of species, I find this statement incomplete, quite apart from its assumption that evolution spells the end of God. Remember, when Darwin
and Russell first presented their hypotheses, it was not only hidebound
Biblical literalists who criticised them. There was also a cohort of genuine
scientists who said that neither man had explained the mechanism of evolution
sufficiently for it to be credible. Their doubts were answered only when that
branch of science known as genetics began. But there is no mention of this,
perhaps because – oops! – the founder of genetics, Gregor Mendel, was one of
those pesky religious people – a Catholic monk no less. Well we can’t let him
into our story of the triumph of science and Enlightenment.
On p.162, Pinker lists the major voices of the
Age of Reason and Enlightenment who opposed slavery. The names he gives are Pascal,
Swift, Voltaire, Samuel Johnson and the Quakers. With the exception of the
deist Voltaire, all of these people were religious believers. [I noted this in my
review of The Better Angels of Our Nature,
where Pinker cited the same names in the same context]. Even more interesting,
if you read James Boswell’s Life of
Johnson (perhaps Pinker hasn’t), you will discover that it is the
free-thinking man of the Enlightenment, James Boswell, who finds all manner of
ingenious arguments for slavery, while it is the conservative Anglican Tory Sam
Johnson who argues passionately against slavery. I definitely do NOT say this
to absolve religious believers of all their many gross and manifest sins, but
simply to show that one cannot attribute all the betterment of the world to one
selected tribe.
I
am wholly in agreement with Pinker when he damns the destructive philosophy of Friedrich
Nietszche, with its Ubermensch fantasies and it thuggish “Will to Power”; but I
do find it interesting that Pinker manages to discuss Nietzsche without once
mentioning his militant atheism (“God is dead”). Let us be clear that Nietzsche
was the first big-note atheist of the modern era. With similar selective
delicacy (or amnesia), Pinker lists all the intellectuals who, following
Nietzsche’s lead, have worshipped tyrants like Stalin, Mao, Mussolini, Castro
etc. , but he manages not to mention that the great majority of them [there
were very few exceptions] were secular humanists and not religious believers (see
Chapter 23, pp.446-447). Indeed most of these listed intellectuals would have
regarded themselves as children of the Enlightenment. Don’t worry though.
Within a few pages, Pinker is having a well-deserved go at the “theocons”
(mainly fundmentalist and evangelical Protestants) who have exerted populist
pressure on recent US elections, so he can console himself that only religious
people do this bad stuff. His justified polemics against anti-Enlightenment, retrogressive
Islam must have helped him affirm his anti-religion views.
My
chief complaint here, then, is that Pinker is too prone to divide the history
of the betterment of humanity into two teams, basically the saved and the
damned. On this side there are all those good secular humanists who embrace
humane values, love and understand science and use reason. On that side there
are all those horrible religious people who are incapable of reasoning,
contribute nothing to science and devote themselves to various forms of
“counter-Enlightenment”. Oh yeah, and there are a few nasty atheists too
(Marxists, postmodernists etc.)
To
give one last example of Pinker’s tendency to create teams, take this
statement, with which, in the main, I heartily agree. Pinker condemns “a long tradition of cultural and religious
elites sneering at the supposedly empty lives of the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat. Cultural criticism can be a thinly disguised snobbery that shades
into misanthropy. In The Intellectuals and the Masses, the critic John
Carey shows how the British literary intelligentsia in the first decades of the
20th century harboured a contempt for the common person which
bordered on the genocidal.” (Chapter 17, p.247) True, but if you take the
trouble to read Carey’s book, you will find that the people Carey most decries
are the Bloomsberries, all of whom would all have (like those admirers of
modern tyrants) regarded themselves as children of the Enlightenment opposing
religion, tradition and so forth just as Pinker does.
But
enough. You are weary of this by now, and my arguments are becoming as
repetitive as Pinker’s own. I reaffirm that I find much to agree with in Enlightenment Now. Yes, material
progress is beneficial, science and reason are good things and [probably] the
mass of humanity are better off now than they have ever been, while admitting
that there is still much poverty and strife in the world. Further, I enjoyed
many of the swipes Pinker takes at postmodernism, hysterical doomsayers,
Nietzsche and various other people who have exerted a malign influence. But by
his own partiality and biases, Pinker paints a very limited picture of how
progress and material betterment happen, assumes that everything beneficial in
the last three hundred years has been achieved by secular humanists like
himself, ignores anything beneficial in history before the Enlightenment, and
divides humanity into neatly-competing teams of the enlightened and the
unenlightened.
I
hope I have enlightened you.
Thank you for an insightful read.
ReplyDeleteI have thoroughly enjoyed Pinker’s past works but thought Enlightenment Now didn’t quite reach the brilliance of his previous arguments. In particular, I noted, in accordance with your ‘saved and the damned’ observations, a persistent habit of playing things a little too fast and convenient.
If you have any inclination, I would love to see your thoughts on what I would argue is his strongest work - The Blank Slate. The book is an effort to lay out an assessment of the intellectual/political lineage of the nature/nurture debate informed by a scientific understandings of human nature. If it’s not baiting the hook too much, I would suggest that you’ll struggle to find a sharper and more reasonable dissection of faddish intellectual nonsense.
Anyway, thank you for your work. Happy reading.