NOTICE TO READERS: For six years, Reid's Reader has been presenting an entirely free service to readers with commentary on books new and old. Reid's Reader
receives no grants or subsidies and is produced each week in many hours
of unpaid work. If you wish to contribute, on an entirely voluntary
basis, to the upkeep of this blog, we would be very grateful if you made
a donation via the PayPal "DONATE" button that now appears at the top
of the index at right. Thank you.]
We feature each week Nicholas Reid's reviews and comments on new and recent books.
We feature each week Nicholas Reid's reviews and comments on new and recent books.
“DEFIANT EARTH – The Fate of
Humans in the Anthropocene” by Clive Hamilton (Allen and Unwin, $NZ 32:99)
Defiant Earth
is a polemic. Experience tells me that polemics come in two varieties. First,
there are the polemics that argue passionately for something. Then there
are the polemics that spend most of their time demolishing other people’s
arguments.
Clive Hamilton, says the blurb, is Professor of Public
Ethics at Charles Sturt University in Australia. As a seasoned
controversialist, he has written three previous books about the dangers of
unfettered humam freedom (The Freedom
Paradox), the potential sefl-destructiveness of the human species (Requiem for a Species) and the folly of
worshipping economic growth as an end in itself (Growth Fetish).
In Defiant Earth he
defends the concept of the Anthropocene and argues that human beings must take
on the responsibility for dealing with it or coping with it. But how we are to
do this is left vague. Most of Hamilton’s polemic is taken up with countering
arguments against the concept of the Anthropocene, and demolishing the logic
and philosophic premises of their proponents. In other words, this is a
“clearing-away-the-rubbish” polemic. It is not a polemic that details a spcific
plan of action.
So
what is the Anthropocene?
Says
Hamilton:
“…the Anthropocene concept would not have been
possible without the emergence of Earth System science in the 1980s and 1990s
as a way of understanding the novel role of humankind in the Earth System…”
(Chapter 1 p.17)
The
term refers to the unique, lasting and specifically human impact on the natural
structures and systems of the Earth. It was first devised in 2000 by the
atmospheric chemist Paul Crutzen. He proposed that “Anthropocene” be added to the official Geological Time Scale, coming after the Holocene
(the last 10,000-or-so years of more-or-less stable climate). The term, as
Hamilton makes clear, does not refer to a superficial human impact on the
Earth’s surface alone, but on the whole Earth System. With carbon emissions,
and the residue of nuclear explosions now imprinted in the geological record,
the Earth’s oceans are more acidic and anthropogenic global warming is
underway. Hamilton’s purpose in this book is to take issue with those who do
not realise the totality of this human distortion of nature, or who put their
trust in arguments that will have no real impact on the situation.
In
his introduction, he makes clear his scepticism of social sciences, which now
have a tendency to talk about human perceptions rather than dealing with
objective physical realities:
“The ‘humans only’ orientation of the social
sciences and humanities is reinforced in ‘mediatized’ societies where total
absorption in representations of reality derived from various forms of media
encourages us to view the ecological crisis as a spectacle that takes place
outsdie the bubble of our existence.” (Introduction p.viii)
He
also sets himself up as an opponent of Enlightenment thinking and what has
traditionally been regarded as humanism:
“…the forces we hoped would make the world a
more civilized place – personal freedoms, democracy, material advance,
technological progress – are in truth paving the way to destruction.” (Introduction
p.xi)
Hamilton’s
first major axiom is that human beings do
indeed have to be seen as unique, and it is only when our uniqueness is
recognised that we can accept our responsibility for doing something about the
global damage our species has done. We are now part of the fabric of the Earth
and its functioning, and human history can no longer be separated from natural
history. We are part of the nature we have defiled, and its reaction to us is
as an equal. We are no longer the Cartesian subject with nature as the object.
Our conceptions of free will break down in the face of the necessity imposed on
us by nature. To some people, this concept is daunting or heretical:
“An
understanding of an independent human history became the foundation of all modern
social sciences, so the convergence – or better the collision – of human and
Earth histories in the Anthropocene kindles the suspicion that all social sciences
and their philosophical foundations have been built on an understanding of the
historical process that is no longer defensible.” (Chapter 1 p.8)
Hamilton
is making it absolutely clear that the sort of anthropocentrism he is
advocating in not the sort that makes us “masters” of nature, or assumes that
other species are simply there for our use and exploitation. He notes the
repeated attempts among many more sentimental ecologists to see human beings as
simply one species among others, as when we are told that we share 98.8 per
cent of our DNA with chimpanzees. But, he remarks:
“Although these attempts to cut humans down
to size are well motivated, aimed as they often have been at countering the
unending violence committed against
other creatures by humans inured to the suffering of others or possessed by a
sense of species entitlement, there is always something desperate about
arguments that equate human beings with chimps, dolphins and dogs when on any
measure the unbridgeable gulf between humans and the rest of creation is
blindingly obvious.” (Chapter 2 p.40)
What
human beings have uniquely is intentionality and conscious responsibility for
the physical condition of the Earth which we have helped to create:
“The philosophical anthropocentrism I develop
diverges from the anthropo-supremacism that brought us the ecological crisis;
yet it also runs contrary to virtually all philosophical understandings of modern
environmentalism and post-humanism.” (Chapter 2 p.49)
Furthermore:
“…against all ethics from Kant onwards,
morality is not to be found in the realm of freedom but is rooted in the realm
of necessity because our duty to care for the Earth must precede all others. It
belongs to us alone. We look across the unbridgeable gulf that separates us
from all other beings; it is a gulf of responsibility. We have it; they don’t.”
(Chapter 2 pp.52-53)
Hamilton’s
next axiom is that the onset of the
Anthropocene cannot be reduced to arguments about the responsibilty of one set
of humanity, as opposed to another, for the permanent damage that has been
done to the Earth System. Much green thought fetishises primitve societies
(rainforest-dwellers etc.), as if their way of living will somehow provide a
model for avoiding ecological crisis – but this ignores the fact that such
people constitute at most about 0.5% per cent of humanity, and their cultures
are not transportable. The Marxist argument fingers economic globalism,
consumerism, Western capitalism and money-making corporations as responsible
for the crisis. [See on this blog my review of Naomi Klein’s This Changes Everything for an
articulate, very informative, version of this argument.] Hamilton in no way
absolves these things of blame. But he points out that Western-style
indistrialisation and consumerism have been embraced enthusiastically by the
“South”, as much as by the “North”, even in countries that are offically not
part of the capitalist world. Globalism has not led to universal brotherhood
but to universal consumerism.
“ China is now the world’s leading
carbon-emitting country by a long way, and the average Chinese person is
responsible for more greenhouse gas emissions than the average European.
Emissions from the South will soon exceed those from the North and it is likely
that in a couple of decades the total historical emissions of the South will
exceed those of the North.” (Chapter 3 p.80)
While
“grand narratives” are anathema to historians and social scientists, Hamilton
believes it is legitimate to see a “grand narrative” in the shared human
responsibility for the Anthropocene.
Hamilton
next attacks the “post-humanism” of many postmodernists. Cultural studies set
out to cut Eurocentrism down to size. Feminism set out to cut men down to size.
Queer theory set out to cut heteromormativity down to size. Now posthumanism
sets out to cut humanity down to size by saying that we are merely one species
among others, and that we are no more important than other species in bringing
about change to our environment. Says Hamilton:
“…
anti-anthopocentrism has the pervese
effect of denying our responsibility for the damage we have caused…. If
the Anthropocene brings a message, it is that’s its time to accept the obvious:
humans stand out from nature as a whole. When Homo sapiens appeared
there was within it some latent property that, when manifested, caused humans
to separate from nature, while always remaining dependent on it. This
natural-unnatural creature, the networked super-agent who straddles the realm
of necessity and the realm of freedom, can exert enormous influence on nature,
even if it cannot control it.” (Chapter 3 pp.98-99)
Next
is Hamilton’s axiom that nature cannot
heal itself of the damage the human species has done. In putting forward
this argument, Hamilton is at odds with the Nietzschean proposition (taken up
by popularisers like Will Self) that humanity is, after all, just a blip on the
scale of geological time; and that were humanity to disappear, nature would
simply resume its course, gradually cleanse the air of pollution and settle
back into its regular rhythms. But such arguments (a.) ignore the indelible
damage that humanity has already done; and (b.) are irresponsible, in that they
not only belittle human uniqueness, but they assume that ultimately no human
action need be taken.
As
I read it, the book’s most essential message is found when Hamilton writes:
“Earth and humans are still in the process
of creation and our pre-eminent task
is to achieve a reconciliation with the Earth at a time when we have an
advanced understanding of its workings and, for good or ill, the power to
change its course.” (Chapter 4 p. 124).
And:
“The struggle to learn how to live
collectively on the Earth and within its limits is the way, the
opportunity for humankind to find its place in the cosmos.” (Chapter 4 p.
125)
Hamilton’s
last axoim is that human freedom is now
constrained by the necessity of our equal partner, the nature with which
we still strive. The Enlightenment myth was that freedom and reason,
released from superstition, would enable us to reshape the world according to
our needs. But the onset of the Anthropocene makes our rational and free choices
more limited. We are not free masters of the universe. It is at this point that
Hamilton takes aim at so-called “eco-engineering”, which is the belief that all
our ecological and environmental problems may be solved by the application of
new and improved technology. In response to suggestion that global warming
could be “fixed” by treating chemically the Earth’s atmosphere, he notes the
real tendency of such thought:
“Rather than slashing the asset value of some
of the globe’s biggest corporations, asking consumers to change their habits,
or imposing unpopular taxes on petrol and coal, this form of solar
geoengineering carries the implicit promise that it will protect the prevailing
politico-economic system, which is why certain conservative American think
tanks that for years have attacked climate science as fraudulent have endorsed
geoengineering as a promising response to global warming.” (Chapter 5, p.14)
Such
thought is no way out of the crisis, and more than are daydreams about sending
lucky people off in spacecraft to other worlds once the Earth no longer
tolerates our species.
As
a philosophical examination of the environmental crisis, Defiant
Earth is a stimulating read. But, as I said at the beginning of this
notice, Hamilton provides no blueprint for our terrestrial salvation. He does
establish the uniqueness of human beings, and the importance of human
responsibility in the face of the Anthropocene. But the future morality he
offers is simply an acceptance of “care" rather than “neglect” when it come to the fate of the Earth. For a plan of action, look elsewhere.
No comments:
Post a Comment